Argument from free will

The argument from free will (also called the paradox of free will, or theological fatalism) contends that omniscience and free will are incompatible, and that any conception of God that incorporates both properties is therefore inherently contradictory.[1][2][3] The argument may focus on the incoherence of people having free will, or else God himself having free will. These arguments are deeply concerned with the implications of predestination, and often seem to echo the standard argument against free will.

Contents

People and their free will

Some arguments against God focus on the supposed incoherence of humankind possessing free will. These arguments are deeply concerned with the implications of predestination.

Moses Maimonides formulated an argument regarding a person's free will, in traditional terms of good and evil actions, as follows:[4]

… "Does God know or does He not know that a certain individual will be good or bad? If thou sayest 'He knows', then it necessarily follows that [that] man is compelled to act as God knew beforehand he would act, otherwise God's knowledge would be imperfect.…"[5]

Various means of reconciling God's omniscience (possession of all possible knowledge) with human free will have been proposed:

Counters reconceptualizing free will

Counters reconceptualizing omniscience

"God is outside of time"

A proposition first offered by Thomas Aquinas.[9] and later C. S. Lewis, it suggests that God's perception of time is different, and that this is relevant to our understanding of our own free will. In his book Mere Christianity, Lewis argues that God is actually outside of time and therefore does not "foresee" events, but rather simply observes them all at once. He explains:

But suppose God is outside and above the Time-line. In that case, what we call "tomorrow" is visible to Him in just the same way as what we call today." All the days are "Now" for Him. He does not remember you doing things yesterday, He simply sees you doing them: because, though you have lost yesterday, He has not. He does not "foresee" you doing things tomorrow, He simply sees you doing them: because, though tomorrow is not yet there for you, it is for Him. You never supposed that your actions at this moment were any less free because God knows what you are doing. Well, He knows your tomorrow's actions in just the same way—because He is already in tomorrow and can simply watch you. In a sense, He does not know your action till you have done it: but then the moment at which you have done it is already "Now" for Him.[10]

An obvious criticism of God being outside of time is that this does not seem to grant free will. Predestination, regardless of how God perceives time, still seems to mean a person's actions will be determined. A logical formulation of this criticism might go as follows:[2]

  1. God timelessly knows choice "C" that a human would claim to "make freely".
  2. If C is in the timeless realm, then it is now-necessary that C.
  3. If it is now-necessary that C, then C cannot be otherwise (this is the definition of “necessary”). That is, there are no actual "possibilities" due to predestination.
  4. If you cannot do otherwise when you act, you do not act freely (Principle of Alternate Possibilities)
  5. Therefore, when you do an act, you will not do it freely.

God's free will

General proof

A simple version of an argument appealing specifically to God's free will:[2]

  1. Yesterday God infallibly believed T. (Supposition of infallible foreknowledge as a subset of omniscience)
  2. If E occurred in the past, it is now-necessary that E occurred then. (Principle of the Necessity of the Past)
  3. It is now-necessary that yesterday God believed T. (1, 2)
  4. Necessarily, if yesterday God believed T, then T. (Definition of “infallibility”)
  5. If p is now-necessary, and necessarily (p → q), then q is now-necessary. (Transfer of Necessity Principle)
  6. So it is now-necessary that T. (3, 4, 5)
  7. If it is now-necessary that T, then God cannot do otherwise. (Definition of “necessary”)
  8. Therefore, God cannot do otherwise. (6, 7)
  9. If God cannot do otherwise when God does an act, God does not act freely. (Principle of Alternate Possibilities)
  10. Therefore, when God does an act, God will not do it freely. (8, 9)
  11. Therefore, an omniscient god cannot have free will. (1, 10)

Dan Barker

Dan Barker's version of the argument is formulated as follows:[11]

  1. God is defined as a personal being who knows everything.
  2. Personal beings have free will.
  3. In order to have free will, you must have more than one option, each of which is avoidable. This means that before you make a choice, there must be a state of uncertainty during a period of potential: you cannot know the future. Even if you think you can predict your decision, if you claim to have free will, you must admit the potential (if not the desire) to change your mind before the decision is final.
  4. A being who knows everything can have no "state of uncertainty". It knows its choices in advance.
  5. A being that knows its choices in advance has no potential to avoid its choices, and therefore lacks free will.
  6. Since a being that lacks free will is not a personal being, a personal being who knows everything cannot exist.
  7. Therefore, a personal God does not exist.

Criticisms of Barker's formulation

The principal criticisms of this argument center around points 1 and 2, though there is some concern regarding point 4. All point numbers refer to Barker's formulation.

Point 1

Theists generally agree that God is a personal being and that God is omniscient[12] but there is some disagreement about whether "omniscient" means:

  1. "knows everything that God chooses to know and that is logically possible to know"; Or instead the slightly stronger:
  2. "knows everything that is logically possible to know"[13]

If omniscient is used in the first sense then the argument's applicability depends on what God chooses to know, and therefore it is not a complete argument against the existence of God. In both cases the argument depends on the assumption that it is logically possible for God to know every choice that he will make in advance of making that choice.

Point 2

The compatibilist school of thought holds that free will is compatible with determinism and fatalism and therefore does not accept the assumptions of point 2. A related line of thought, which goes back at least to Boethius, holds that God observing someone making a choice does not constrain their choice, although this is in the context of human free will[14][15]

Point 4

One criticism of the Argument from Free Will is that in point 4 of the proof it simply assumes that foreknowledge and free will are incompatible. It uses circular logic to "prove" this, by simply stating that "a being that knows its choices in advance has no potential to avoid its choices". Point 4 is therefore saying, in essence, "A being that knows its choices in advance has no free will, and therefore has no free will". By assuming what it is trying to prove, that point undermines the entire argument.

Specifically, point 4 commits the modal fallacy of assuming that because some choice is known to be true, it must be necessarily true (i.e. there is no way it could possibly be false).[16] Logically, the truth value of some proposition cannot be used to infer that the same proposition is necessarily true.

Using logical terminology and applying it to AFFW, there is a marked distinction between the statement "It is impossible (for God to know a future action to be true and for that action to not occur)" and the statement "If God knows that a future action is true, then it is impossible for that action to not occur." While the two statements may seem to say the same thing, they are not logically equivalent. The second sentence is false because it commits the modal fallacy of saying that a certain action is impossible, instead of saying that the two propositions (God knows a future action to be true, and that action does not occur) are jointly impossible. Simply asserting that God knows a future action does not make it impossible for that action not to occur. The confusion comes in mistaking a semantic relation between two events for a causal relation between two events.

With these assumptions more explicitly stated, the proof becomes:

  1. Assume that person X has free will (assumption).
  2. By the definition of free will, at any point in time, X can choose to do any action A, where A belongs to A(T), the set of all actions that X is physically capable of at time T (definition of free will).
  3. At time T, person X will choose to do action A (i.e. a person cannot logically choose to do both A and not A) (Law of the Excluded Middle).
  4. Assume that an omniscient God exists (assumption).
  5. By the definition of omniscience, God knows everything that will happen at any point in time (definition of omniscience).
  6. From 3. and 5., God knows that at time T, person X will choose to do action A (logical conclusion).
  7. Therefore, person X must do action A at time T.

This claims to prove that at time T, person X is unable to do any action other than A. However, you could also remove steps 4–6, and arrive at the same conclusion. This is called logical determinism, and it suffers from the same modal fallacy as AFFW. If a certain proposition is true, that does not imply that the proposition is logically necessary. Once you remove the invalid assertion, then the argument for logical determinism is shown to be false. Similarly, when that same invalid assertion is removed from AFFW ("by the definitions of 'knowledge' and 'choice', if one knows for certain what choice one will make in the future, one will not be able to make the opposite choice"), the proof is shown to be false.[17]

Response to criticisms

In response to the above criticisms:

Point 1

Both of the interpretations of omnisicience referred to in the criticism include a qualification: what is chosen to be known, or what is logical. So the proposed definitions impose limitations on this God. So saying that Barker assumes "that it is logically possible for God to know every choice that he will make in advance of making that choice" is self-defeating as an objection. Firstly, it contradicts the traditional concept of the omnipotent, infallible God in Christianity that Barker is responding to; and secondly, it leads logically to the position that humans could potentially know more than this God.

Point 2

It is not enough to simply take the position that free will is compatible with determinism. The argument against free will is not about "God observing someone making a choice", it is about perfect foreknowledge that something will necessarily happen, negating that there is choice. If the future is perfectly known, it is fixed, and there are no choices.[18]

Point 4

The charge that the argument against free will assumes that foreknowledge and free will are incompatible (and therefore circular), is untenable. The incompatibility stems from the claim of omnisicence. It is a quite reasonable position to take that "a being that knows its choices in advance has no potential to avoid its choices." The challenge for the theist is to provide a reasonable account of how, if all is infallibly known in advance, that it is even possible that anything could be different.

The real problem is in the way that concepts of Gods are developed, and the extraordinary claims that are made, which are not based on empirical evidence.

The objection on the grounds of committing a modal fallacy is also untenable. In the case of omniscience, foreknowledge of what will happen tomorrow means that it is indeed logically necessary that it happens, with no possibility that it will not. Otherwise it is not omniscience. So the truth of "X will happen tomorrow" is equivalent to "it is necessarily the case that X will happen tomorrow".

In addition, the new proof provided is poorly constructed. Omniscience, or foreknowledge, is placed incorrectly in the sequence (starting at step 4), after the choice is made. Clearly foreknowledge, by definition, occurs before the choice is made. So if at a point in time before T there is infallible knowledge that X will choose to do action A at time T, then it is incorrect that at time T X can choose to do any action because X is committed to A and only A. The claim of free will collapses. The specification is very different with and without the inclusion of omniscience.

The objection that the "confusion comes in mistaking a semantic relation between two events for a causal relation between two events" can be criticised as at the very least presenting a false dilemma, or at worst begging the question. The false dilemma stems from the lack of specificity of how the infallible divine foreknowledge can occur. Begging the question stems from the assumption that the infallible, divine foreknowledge is not based on causality. Omniscience, knowing everything to come, that the future is settled and fixed, can only make sense if determinism is true.[19] If everything is causally determined, then it is feasible that perfect knowledge of the causal relationships will produce perfect knowledge of what is to come: omniscience.

See also

References

  1. ^ See the various controversies on God's Omniscience, and in particular on the critical notion of Foreknowledge
  2. ^ a b c Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Foreknowledge and Free Will
  3. ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Foreknowledge and Free Will
  4. ^ Though Moses Maimonides was not arguing against the existence of God, but rather for the incompatibility between the full exercise by God of his omniscience and genuine human free will, his argument is considered by some as affected by Modal Fallacy. See, in particular, the article by Prof. Norman Swartz for Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Foreknowledge and Free Will and specifically Section 6: The Modal Fallacy
  5. ^ The Eight Chapters of Maimonides on Ethics (Semonah Perakhim), edited, annotated, and translated with an Introduction by Joseph I. Gorfinkle, pp. 99–100. (New York: AMS Press), 1966.
  6. ^ Gospel of Thomas 3
  7. ^ Holy Bible, 2 Peter 1:10, Webster's Encyclopedic Dictionary
  8. ^ The Philosopher's Handbook, Stanley Rosen, ed., Random House Reference, New York, 2000.
  9. ^ See also Divine Providence versus the concept of Fate
  10. ^ C. S. Lewis Mere Christianity Touchstone:New York, 1980 p.149
  11. ^ The Freewill Argument for the Nonexistence of God by Dan Barker Freethought Today, August 1997 [1]
  12. ^ see eg Richard Swinburne Does God Exist? of The Catechism of the Catholic Church
  13. ^ see eg John Polkinghorne
  14. ^ see eg the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article cited above for details of the Boethian view
  15. ^ The controversy about this was so well-known in Chaucer's day that he has a somewhat satirical digression on it in The Nun's Priest's Tale.Nun's Priest's Tale Lines 3234–3251
  16. ^ Prof. Norman Swartz, The Modal Fallacy
  17. ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Foreknowledge and Free Will: The Modal Fallacy
  18. ^ Grayling, A.C., The Meaning of Things. Phoenix, 2007, p. 128.
  19. ^ Grayling, A.C., The Meaning of Things. Phoenix, 2007, p. 128.

Further reading

External links